Like Life was a 2018 sculpture exhibition at New York's Met Breuer
Museum. Its catalogue of the same name not only illustrates many of the
exhibits but also presents several analytical essays of a substantial and
challenging nature. The catalogue is worthy of recognition in its own right and
can be appreciated by anyone interested in art, even those who have not seen
the exhibition. It presents a significant contribution to our appreciation of
the three-dimensional art which we tend to label “sculpture” and its insights go
significantly beyond what may be described as art criticism. The convoluted
nature of this description will be understood by anyone who reads this book,
because its approach is always to question the received values through which we
interpret our experience of art. Indeed, these essays might even challenge our
understanding of anything we might see through the lens of prejudice,
assumption or merely interpretation. In short, everything. Like Life, the
catalogue, thus becomes almost a disturbing experience. We know much more by
the end, but only by realizing how little of ourselves and our perception that
we actually understand.
Like Life is obviously a pun on life-like. It may also be read as a
command, associated with liking life, which would be ironic, since the still
life that these forms present is translated in many languages not as still, but
dead. One of the threads that binds the discussion is that when sculpture
becomes literally like life, it has generally been dismissed by critics as artefact, thus relegated and denied the label art. And at the heart of the discussion is the
use of colour.
Modelled on a misplaced assumption that classical sculpture was
expressed via a visual language derived from the unblemished whiteness of
marble, the story of sculpture unfolded via this misunderstood desire to reproduce
classical values through both purity of whiteness and fineness of finish. Like
Life not only reminds us that these classical works were originally polychrome,
it also asserts that this false set of values conveniently coincided with the
European view that whiteness was always superior, and that anything coloured
was, by inspection, inferior. Anything polychrome was thus firmly relegated to
the ambit of the artisan, not the artist. And it was this assumption that for
centuries effectively separated the worlds of sculpture and painting.
The original Met Breuer exhibition displayed sculpture from the later
medieval era up to the present day, but non-chronologically. It juxtaposed
items to illustrate themes, contrasts and contradictions in a thoroughly
stimulating way. The catalogue of Like Life also does this, but the
intellectual arguments within its texts are perhaps even more arresting than
the visual punches the exhibition delivered.
Why is it that in painting, an attempt to render flesh flesh-coloured is
normal even laudable,, whereas in sculpture it has for centuries been seen as
devaluing the object? Why is it that we expect a sculptor to start with stone,
wood or wax and work it into an image of their choice, rather than mould
directly from the human form? Why do we still reject realism, when that realism
depicts the everyday objects we normally do not associate with art? Why do
expect idealised human forms, rather than real people, defects, foibles and
all? Why is it that the sculpted naked human form still generally does not
depict genitals? Why do we devalue sculpture that is modelled directly from
life? What becomes clear quite early on in this journey through a history
of sculpture is that the process it illustrates could be applied to any
artistic form upon which we are willing to offer opinions. It could be painting,
music, theatre, literature, poetry, etc. Upon what basis do we describe value
or worth, upon what set of rules do we ascribe artistic value? And what
controlling role do our presumptions play in editing what we see, or at least
our interpretation of what we see? And, perhaps most important of all, if we
are slaves to our presumptions, who or what generated them?
Functionality has always been a consideration. If an object is wholly
divorced from use, then it has always been more likely, in our Western mode of
thinking, that is, to be regarded as art. Mannequins in shopfronts, just like
polychrome inflated cherubs decorating altarpieces, have always been seen as
functional rather than artistic. A sculptor who chisels at a block of jasper to
model a bust produces art, sometimes, whereas an undertaker who plaster-casts a
death mask does not. But then, a death mask is not representing life, is it? It
shows a form incapable of movement, after all. But then how can we see a still
life as art, because that cannot move, can it?
Viewing the exhibition itself and certainly reading the catalogue can
literally change the way a person looks at the world. A flea market that used
to offer repeated tables of junk, now presents objects that have a reason to
exist. What the observer must try to glean is why the maker of the object
decided to represent that thing, in that way, in that material and in that
colour. Like Life thus leads to complication. What previously was seen, and
perhaps largely ignored, becomes objectified, separate, worthy of being looked
at actively, rather than received in a passive, even dismissive way. Not many
books have this kind of effect on their readers.
Like Life is as much a challenge as it is a presentation. Yes, we are
presented with images of sculpture and asked to react. But the commentary often
offers such a radically different approach from that which we may assume that
it really does challenge us to reinterpret and re-evaluate our presumptions. It
is what art is supposed to do, isn’t it?